Sobre la noción de información genéticasemantica y excepcionalidad

  1. Etxeberria Agiriano, Arantza
  2. García Azkonobieta, Tomás
Revista:
Theoria: an international journal for theory, history and foundations of science

ISSN: 0495-4548

Ano de publicación: 2004

Volume: 19

Número: 50

Páxinas: 209-230

Tipo: Artigo

Outras publicacións en: Theoria: an international journal for theory, history and foundations of science

Resumo

El objetivo de este artículo es analizar ciertas críticas a la aplicación de la noción de información en biología, teniendo en cuenta tanto la historia del concepto como las diferentes posiciones actuales. Creemos que la motivación principal de las críticas es negar que los genes sean un factor causal excepcional en el desarrollo, y favorecer la imagen de la vida como un sistema organizado que requiere diferentes recursos. Aunque compartimos el rechazo del reduccionismo genético, argumentamos que éste no es atribuible a la analogía informacional y que, por tanto, no es necesario abandonarla completamente.

Referencias bibliográficas

  • Alberch, P. (1982). "Developmental constraints in evolutionary processes", en J.T. Bonner (ed.), Evolution and development. Berlín: Springer-Verlag, pp. 313-332
  • - (1989). "The logic of monsters: Evidence for internal constraints in development and evolution", Geobois 12, 21-57
  • Atlan, H., and M. Koppel (1990). "The cellular computer DNA: program or data", Bulletin of Mathematical Biology 52 (3), 335-343
  • Barbieri, M. (en prensa). "Biology with information and meaning", History and Philosophy of the Life Sciences
  • Beurton, P.J.; R. Falk and H.J. Rheinberger (eds.) (2000). The concept of the gene in development and epistemological perspectives: Historical and epistemological perspectives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
  • Bowler, P. (1983). Evolution: The history of an idea. Berkeley: University of California Press
  • Cairns, J.; G.S. Stent and J.D. Watson (eds.) (1966). Phage and the origins of Molecular Biology. Cold Spring Harbor: Cold Spring Harbor Laboratory of Quantitative Biology
  • Clark, A., and J. Toribio (1994). "Doing without representing?", Synthese 101, 401-431
  • Crick, F.H.C. (1958). "On Protein Synthesis", Symposium of the Society for Experimental Biology 12, 138-163
  • Dawkins, R. (1976). The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press
  • - (1982). The Extended Phenotype. Oxford: Oxford University Press
  • Eldredge, N., and S. Salthe (1984). "Hierarchy and evolution", en R. Dawkins and M. Ridley (eds.), Oxford surveys in evolutionary biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 184-208
  • Emmeche, C. (1999). "The Sarkar Challenge to Biosemiotics: Is there any information in the cell?", Semiotica 127 (1/4), 273-293
  • Etxeberria, A., and A. Moreno (2001). "From complexity to simplicity: Nature and Symbols", Biosystems 60 (1-3), 143-157
  • Gilbert, S.F. (1982). "Intellectual traditions in the Life Sciences: Molecular Biology and Biochemistry", Perspectives in Biology and Medicine 26 (1), 151-162
  • - (1997). Developmental Biology. Sunderland (MA): Sinauer, 5. th ed
  • - and S. Sarkar (2000). "Embracing complexity: Organicism for the 21st century", Developmental Systems 219, 1-9
  • Godfrey-Smith, P. (2000). "On the theoretical role of 'Genetic Coding'", Philosophy of Science 67, 26-44
  • Goodwin, B. (1994). How the leopard changed its spots. London: Weidefeld & Nicolson
  • Grene, M. (1987). "Hierarchies in biology", American Scientist 75, 504-509
  • Griesemer, J.R. (1992). "The informational gene and the substantial body: On the generalization of evolutionary theory by abstraction". Manuscrito no publicado
  • Griffiths, P.E. (2001). "Genetic information: A metaphor in search of a theory", Philosophy of Science 68, 394-412
  • - and R.D. Gray (1994). "Developmental systems and evolutionary explanation"', Journal of Philosophy 91, 277-304
  • - and R.D. Gray (2001). "Darwinism and developmental systems", en S. Oyama, P.E. Griffiths and R.D. Gray (eds.), Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge: MIT Press, pp. 195-218
  • - and E.M. Neumann-Held (1999). 'The many faces of the gene", Bioscience 49 (8), 656-662
  • Hall, B.K., and W.M. Olson (eds.) (2003). Keywords and concepts in Evolutionary Developmental Biology. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press
  • Hull, D. (1980). "Individuality and selection", Annual Review of Ecological Systems 11, 311-332
  • Hofstadter, D.R. (1987). Gödel, Escher, Bach. Barcelona: Tusquets Editores
  • Huxley, J. (1942). Evolution: The modern synthesis. London: Allen and Unwin
  • Jablonka, E., and M. Lamb (1995). Epigenetic inheritance and evolution: The Lamarckian dimension. Oxford: Oxford University Press
  • Judson, H.F. (1979). The Eighth Day of Creation. The makers of the revolution in Biology. New York: Simon and Schuster
  • Kay, L.E. (1997). "Cybernetics, information, life: The emergence of scriptural representations of heredity", Configurations 5, 23-91
  • - (2000). Who wrote the Book of Life: A history of the Genetic Code. Stanford: Stanford University Press
  • Keller, E.F. (2000). The century of the gene. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press
  • Lewens, T. (2002). "Development aid: on ontogeny and ethics", Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 33, 195-217
  • Maienschein, J. (1992). "Gene: Historical perspectives", en E.F. Keller and E.A. Lloyd (eds.): Keywords in evolutionary biology. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press, pp. 122-127
  • Maynard Smith, J. (1986). The problems of Biology. Oxford: Oxford University Press
  • - (2000a). "The concept of Information in Biology", Philosophy of Science 67 (2), 177-194
  • - (2000b). La construcción de la vida: genes, embriones y evolución. Barcelona: Crítica
  • -, R. Burian, S. Kauffman, P. Alberch, J. Campbell, B. Goodwin, R. Laude, D. Raup and L. Wolpert (1985). "Developmental constraints and evolution: A perspective from the Mountain Lake Conference on development and evolution", Quaterly Reviews of Biology 60, 265-287
  • - and E. Szathmary (1995). The major transitions of evolution. Oxford: W.H. Freeman
  • Mayr, E. (1982). The growth of biological thought. Diversity, evolution and inheritance. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press
  • Müller, G.B., and S.A. Newman (eds.) (2003). Origination of organismal form. Beyond the gene in Developmental and Evolutionary Biology. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press
  • Morange, M. (1998). A history of Molecular Biology. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press
  • Murray, T. (1997). "Genetic exceptionalism and future diaries: Is genetic information different from other forms of medical information?", en M. Rothstein (ed.): Genetic secrets: Protecting privacy and confidenciality. New Haven: Yale University Press, pp. 60-76
  • Olby, R. (1974). The path to the double helix. The discovery of DNA. New York: Dover
  • Oyama, S. (1985). The ontogeny of information. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
  • - (2000). "Causal democracy and causal contributions in DST", Philosophy of Science 67 (Proceedings), 332-347
  • -, P.E. Griffiths and R.D. Gray (eds.) (2001). Cycles of contingency: Developmental systems and evolution. Cambridge (MA): MIT Press
  • Pattee, H.H. (1977). "Dynamic and linguistic modes of complex systems", Int. J. General Systems 3, 259-266
  • Sarkar, S. (1996). "Biological information: A skeptical look at some central dogmas of molecular biology", en S. Sarkar (ed.): The philosophy and history of molecular biology: new perspectives. Dordrecht: Kluwer
  • - (1997). "Decoding "coding" - Information and DNA", Bioscience 46 (11), 858-864
  • - (1998). Genetics and reductionism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press
  • Schrödinger, E. (1944). What is Life? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. [Trad. cast.: ¿Qué es la vida? Barcelona: Tusquets, 1984)
  • Sterelny, K. (2000). "The 'Genetic Program' Program: A Commentary on Maynard Smith on Information in Biology", Philosophy of Science 67 (2), 195-201
  • - and P.E. Griffiths (1999). Sex and Death. An Introduction to Philosophy of Biology. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press
  • Stuart, C. (1985a). "Physical models of biological information and adaptation", Journal of Theoretical Biology 113, 441-454
  • Umerez, J. (2001). "Howard Pattee's Theoretical Biology. A radical epistemological stance to approach life, evolution and complexity", Biosystems 60 (1-3), 159-177
  • Varela, F. (1979). Principles of Biological Autonomy. New York: Elsevier North Holland
  • Wheeler, M., and A. Clark (1999). "Genic representation: reconciling content and causal complexity", British Journal of Philosophy of Science 50, 103-135
  • Watson, J.D., and F.H.C. Crick (1953). "Genetical implications of the structure of Deoxyribose Nucleic Acid", Nature 171, 964-967
  • Waddington, C.H. (ed.) (1976). Hacia una Biología Teórica. Madrid: Alianza, pp. 277-280
  • Yoxen, E.J. (1979). "Where does Schroedinger's "What is Life?" belong in the history of Molecular Biology?", History of Science, 17, 17-52